10 tips for sharpening your logical thinking
Logical thinking helps
you discern the truth, solve problems, and make good decisions -- unless your
logic is flawed. Here are a few principles that will help ensure correct
reasoning.
1: The conditional statement
Have you ever dropped
your smartphone into water? Not good, correct? Let's assume, for purposes of
this article, that every time it happens, without exception, that phone is
ruined. In other words, this statement is true: "If you drop your smartphone
into water, then it will become ruined."
This statement, in
logic, is known as a conditional statement. The first part of the sentence
states a condition or requirement. The second part of the sentence states the
result of that condition. If the condition is fulfilled, the result will occur.
If you've done any application programming, you doubtless have worked with
conditional statements. The principles of conditional statements are the same
for logical thinking.
2: Understanding premise and conclusion shorthand
The two parts of a
conditional statement have specific terms with respect to logic. The first part
is called a premise, and the second part is called a conclusion. Within a
conditional statement, if a premise is true, the conclusion will be too,
because it follows, or results from, the truth of the premise.
Sometimes, in
shorthand, you will see the abbreviations "p" and "q" for
"premise" and "conclusion," respectively. The causal
relationship (the "then") is indicated by an arrow: →. Here,
"p" would represent "If you drop your smartphone into
water," "q" would represent "the smartphone will become
ruined," and → would represent the "then." The general nature of
a conditional statement can be represented as p → q.
Once we understand the
structure of an original conditional statement in terms of p and q, we can
understand three other statements related to it. They are the converse, the
inverse, and the contrapositive. Knowing these three is important to avoid
faulty reasoning and to detect faulty reasoning by others.
3: The converse statement
The converse of the
original conditional statement simply reverses the premise and the conclusion.
In shorthand terms, therefore, the converse is q → p. In our smartphone
example, the converse statement would be: "If your smartphone is ruined,
then it was because you dropped it into water."
As you can see, in
this case the converse is not true, because a smartphone can be ruined in many
other ways besides dropping it into water. Similarly, though someone who lives
in Florida lives in the United States, not everyone who lives in the United
States lives in Florida. Assuming that the converse is true, in fact, leads to
the fallacy of the "false syllogism":
·
If a phone is dropped into water, it is ruined.
·
John's phone is ruined.
·
Therefore, John's phone must have been dropped into water.
An example of similar
potentially faulty reasoning is the following:
·
Every computer that has virus x has symptom y.
·
Joe's computer has symptom y.
·
Therefore, Joe's computer has virus x.
This reasoning is
faulty for the same reason — namely, that a computer could have symptom y for
other reasons. A correct analysis would be the following:
·
If a computer has virus x, then it has symptom y.
·
Joe's computer has virus x.
·
Therefore, Joe's computer has symptom y.
The false syllogism is
better illustrated this classic way:
·
Dogs have four legs.
·
Cats have four legs.
·
Therefore, dogs are cats.
4: The inverse statement
The inverse of the
original statement keeps the original premise and original conclusion but
negates each one. In shorthand, the inverse is ~p → ~q.
The inverse of the
smartphone statement would be: "If you do not drop your smartphone into
water, your smartphone will not become ruined." Sometimes, the inverse is
true. But other times, such as with our example, it isn't. A smartphone can be
ruined in many ways. Therefore, even if we refrain from dropping the phone into
water, it doesn't prevent other bad things from happening to it. The inverse of
the virus statement would be: "If a computer does not have virus x, it
will not have symptom y." This statement might not be true if symptom y
can result from reasons other than virus x.
Be careful of inverse
reasoning.
5: The contrapositive statement
The contrapositive is
either the converse of the inverse or the inverse of the converse. That is, it
involves a negation of both the premise and the conclusion, along with their
reversal. Our smartphone contrapositive would be: "If your smartphone is
not ruined, then you did not drop it into water." The virus contrapositive
would be "If a computer does not have symptom y, then it does not have
virus x." In shorthand, the contrapositive is ~q → ~p.
Assuming the truth of
the original conditional statement, the contrapositive is the only alternative
statement that will always be true.
6: Necessary conditions
Closely related to the
conditional and related statements are the ideas of necessary conditions and
sufficient conditions.
A necessary condition
is one that must be met for a certain result to be achieved. For a smartphone
not to be ruined, it must be kept out of water. Therefore "keeping a
smartphone out of water" is necessary to prevent it from being ruined. The
absence of virus x is necessary to have assurance that a computer does not have
symptom y.
I know the objections
you are raising right now, but keep reading for my further points.
7: Sufficient conditions
A sufficient condition
is one that, if met, absolutely guarantees the occurrence of a certain result —
that is, a result that is dependent on that condition. Dropping a smartphone
into water is sufficient for ruining that phone. Doing so guarantees that the
phone is ruined. The presence of virus x is a sufficient condition for a
computer to exhibit symptom y.
8: Necessary but not sufficient
A condition can be
necessary but not sufficient. Keeping your smartphone out of water is necessary
for preventing its ruin. However, even if you do so, your smartphone could be
ruined in other ways, such as being crushed by a car or dropped from a height.
In the same way, even if virus x is absent from the computer, they system could
still display symptom y for some other reason. Therefore, keeping a smartphone
out of water, and keeping virus x off a computer are necessary but not
sufficient conditions for preventing smartphone ruin or the presence of symptom
y.
9: Sufficient but not necessary
Similarly, a condition
can be sufficient but not necessary. Dropping the smartphone into water is a
sufficient condition for ruining it. However, it is not a necessary condition
for ruining it. Having virus x is a sufficient condition for symptom y.
However, if symptom y can arise from other causes, having virus x is not a
necessary condition.
10: Neither necessary nor sufficient
A condition can be neither necessary nor
sufficient with respect to a result. To prevent the ruin of your smartphone, it
is neither necessary nor sufficient that its area code begin with an even
number. To prevent virus x, it is neither necessary nor sufficient that the
system unit have a property tag.
Tidak ada komentar:
Posting Komentar